The
Matter of Time
by George Musser
If any subject deserves
an interdisciplinary treatment, it is time. Our experience of time
is so fundamental and so mysterious that it takes all areas of human
endeavor to come to grips with it. Historically, scientific and
artistic ideas of time have played off one another, and I think that
remains true today. In this short talk, I’ll focus on the scientific
ideas, but as I’ll mention toward the end of my remarks, those ideas
have evolved in parallel with social and cultural attitudes toward
time.
Almost all the major
questions of modern physics boil down to an inability to understand
time and its conjoined twin, space. Many of these conundrums arise
from the particular way of conceptualizing time that physicists have
adopted, so let me begin with it. This conception of time has been
extremely useful in making physics the most precise of all sciences.
Yet it has its limits and those limits have become increasingly
pressing.
Physicists conceptually
divide nature into two elements: (a) the state of the world, and (b)
the laws of physics. The state of the world is defined in space. In
classical mechanics, such as the rules that govern a pool table, the
state consists of the positions and velocities of objects. The laws
of physics operate in time. They take one state to the next. These
laws work both ways: we can run the laws in reverse to reconstruct
what the world used to be like.
This division of labor
leads us to a picture known as the spacetime diagram

Figure 1-
A spacetime diagram represents time spatially. A
tilted line represents the path of moving object. A 45-degree line
represents the path of a light beam. People moving at different
speeds slice spacetime into space and time differently.
For these purposes, we’re
not worried about all the spatial relationships that objects can
have, so we can represent all the spatial dimensions with a single
dimension, the horizontal axis of this diagram. The state of the
world is defined along this direction. By applying the laws of
physics, you can take the state and predict the state at any time in
the future. Over time, objects trace out an entire line. A car
moving at a steady speed, for example, corresponds to a straight,
tilted line. So you can lay out time like a spatial dimension.
This geometric idea of
time as a gridline underpins everything I’ll say about time today.
Spatializing time seems so commonsensical that even many
non-physicists forget how remarkable it is. We do not perceive time
as anything remotely resembling a spatial dimension. We routinely
draw the path of a baseball thrown into the air as an arc, but we do
not directly see it that way. Rather, we see the world unfold from
one moment to the next.
What gives this
spatialized view of time more than metaphorical significance is that
how you divvy up space and time can change. Spacetime gets sliced
differently into space and time differently depending on your
velocity. To the driver of the car, it looks like he’s stationary
and the rest of the world shoots by. The speed of a car looks like
zero if you’re driving, 55 mph if you’re on the ground, or 110 mph
in a head-on collision. The moving car becomes, to the driver, a
fixed reference point, and he divides up space differently than the
observer on the ground. This is the principle of relativity first
articulated by Galileo.
Einstein showed that even
time looks different depending on your velocity. The reason is that
the speed of light, unlike the speed of a car, looks the same
to every observer. For the speed of light to remain the same, you
can’t simply determine relative speed by adding or subtracting,
because then you could exceed the speed of light; instead you need a
more complicated relative-velocity formula that mixes space and
time. Loosely speaking, for the speed of light to remain the same as
you speed up, the passage of time must slow down for you. On a
spacetime diagram, the faster you go, the more the line representing
your velocity gets tilted, approaching the diagonal line that
represents the speed of light. Each of us moves into the future at
his or her own pace.
You
have to take care with spatializing time. People often talk of time
as the fourth dimension, but that doesn’t mean space and time
are the same; the two may be related, but they’re still distinct.
Time plays a special role in nature. This distinctiveness is the
heart of many of the deep problems in modern physics.
Maybe the most important
is what physicists refer to as causality: the principle that there
is an objective distinction between cause and effect. More
precisely, if we have two events ‘A’ and ‘B’, event ‘A’ can help
cause event ‘B’ if it (a) precedes it in time, and (b) is close
enough to exert an influence on ‘B’. If these two conditions are
true for one observer, they’re true for all observers, no matter how
fast those observers are moving.

Figure 2 -
Time is structured to ensure that cause-effect
relations are objective. If one person sees an event ‘A’ cause, or
help to cause, an event ‘B’, so will other people, even when they’re
moving at different speeds. The time interval between ‘A’ and ‘B’
might differ, but one will always precede the other.
For example, in pool, if
the cue ball hits the 4-ball and the 4-ball knocks the 8-ball into a
pocket, this sequence will be the same for everyone looking on.
Nobody will see the reverse sequence in which the 8-ball jumps out
of the pocket and hits the 4.
The reason causality
holds is that there’s a limit to how much space and time mix. The
space axis always remains below the line representing the speed of
light, and the time axis always remains above it. Otherwise, you
might get a case where space and time switch places, such that
events that occur sequentially to a slow observer occur
simultaneously to a faster one and in reverse order to an even
faster one. If such reversals happened, you could set up time loops
in which it wouldn’t be clear what is cause and what is effect. And
that might allow for paradoxes—the same kinds of paradoxes that can
arise in time travel, such as events that cause themselves or,
conversely, prevent themselves from happening. It would give a whole
new twist to the chicken-and-egg problem if a chicken could lay the
egg that she hatched from.
So time looks almost but
not quite like a spatial dimension. In space, you have freedom to
move around and you can see a whole landscape spread out before you.
That’s obviously not true in time. Our experience of time is
different from that of space in several ways.
First, we experience that
time is unidirectional—the so-called arrow of time. The past is
different from the future, even though the laws of physics are
bidirectional. The classic example is an egg breaking. We see eggs
crack and then break open, but never the opposite, an egg
spontaneously healing its cracks. How do you reconcile the
unidirectionality we see with the bidirectionality of the laws of
physics?
The thinking, going back
to the 19th century, is that time itself has no directionality and
that the arrow is an emergent property of nature: something that’s
not present at the foundations, but arises in the aggregate. The
arrow characterizes the motion not of individual molecules, but of a
mass of molecules. After all, there’s no such thing as an egg,
broken or otherwise, in the basic laws. The difference between eggs
in various states of repair, and therefore the directionality of the
process, has to do with how the molecules are organized. The fresh
egg is the most highly organized, the broken egg slightly less so,
the shattered egg even less.
What I mean by the word
“organized” is that there are more ways for the egg to be a little
broken than pristine, and even more ways to be completely broken. So
just by the laws of probability, the egg is more likely to be broken
than not, and if you start with a pristine egg, practically anything
the molecules do is likely to lead to breakage. The real question,
then, is why you ever had a pristine egg to begin with. The
probabilistic progression implies that whatever came before was even
less probable, and before that, even less probable, all the way to
the origin of the universe. The universe was originally in a very
particular state.
Over time, the universe
approaches the most probable, most generic state possible, a
condition of complete dissipation known as heat death. Living things
resist this overall trend toward degeneration; we carve out little
pockets of order in an increasingly disorderly world. But in bucking
the trend, we actually contribute to the overall degeneration. The
act of living literally kills the universe.
And you know what makes
it even more tragic? It’s forgetting that causes the most
damage. Because the laws of physics are reversible, whenever we
forget, the world must take on the burden of remembering for us.
Forgetting—erasing—is essential to the process of creation. Art is
tragic in many ways, but surely this is the worst.
The second way that time
differs from space is that not only do we perceive a directionality
to time, we perceive a “flow” to time: the sense that only the
present moment is real. Yet physics and philosophical logic hold
that time is laid out in its entirety—that the past and future exist
equally. Otherwise, how could different observers slice up time
differently? Whose “flow” would be right? Most scientists would
argue that past, present, and future all exist, and we move among
them like a car driving down the road. Some, to be sure, think it’s
the physicists’ notion of time that should give.
The flow of time raises
two questions. Why do we perceive it? That is, why don’t we see time
as spatialized? Presumably that, too, has something to do with what
it means to be alive. An even deeper question is: If the world is
laid out and everything is preordained, does time matter at all? The
state of the world at one time determines it at all times. The past
and future exist in the present, as T.S. Eliot wrote:
Time present and time
past
Are both perhaps present in time future,
And time future contained in time past.
If all time is eternally present
All time is unredeemable.
Third and finally,
there’s a specific technical sense in which time doesn’t seem to
matter at all. This is something that comes out of Einstein’s
general theory of relativity. In this theory, not only do space and
time unite, but they can distort,

Figure 3 -
Spacetime not only can be divided up differently, it
can distort, producing what we perceive as the force of gravity. The
fact that time can distort is one of the reasons physicists suspect
that it is not truly fundamental to nature.
They’re malleable. We
become aware of this as the force of gravity. The problem comes when
you try to describe the distortion of space as a process occurring
in time. You find that the shapes space takes are mathematically
different, but physically equivalent. So nothing truly changes. The
world according to physics is frozen in place, incapable of true
change, which flies in the face of what we see. This is one of the
biggest reasons why it has been hard to unite general relativity
with other theories of physics.
Lecturers on physics
often mention the malleability of space without explaining what it
means, so let me digress for just a moment to flesh it out a little
bit. The idea is that our Earth, for example, bends both space and
time. At the surface of our planet, the fractional distortion is
about one part in a billion. The temporal distortion is a distortion
to how fast clocks tick. The closer you are to the center of the
Earth, the slower a clock will tick; clocks on the ground tick more
slowly than they do in orbit. Space also gets distorted, altering
the distance between objects, but most of the things we deal with,
like baseballs, move so slowly that they don’t probe much of space.
Their path through spacetime is mostly a path through time.

Figure 4a -
In the conventional view, time is fundamental and
defines the motion and oscillation of objects: a gear turns, a
pendulum swings, and a heart beats once per second. In the
relational view, time is derivative. Objects bear certain
relationships to one another—a gear turns once per swing of a
pendulum or beat of a heart—and we introduce the abstraction of time
to make it easier to describe this web of relationships, much as we
introduce money to simplify economic transactions.
What physicists do is
define a notion of spacetime distance that includes both spatial
distance and time duration. The baseball naturally follows a path
that maximizes its spacetime distance; this is the spacetime
counterpart to a straight line in space. Now, because the spacetime
distance for a baseball is mostly just the time distance, this means
that the baseball wants to maximize the duration of its
flight, as measured by its own internal clock. And that means it
wants to spend as much time far from the Earth’s center as it can.
When it’s far out, its internal clock ticks faster, so the baseball
maximizes its flight time out there. The ball wants to move slowly
at the top of its arc and faster at the bottom, so it can linger as
long as possible at the top. Thus it decelerates as it moves up, or
conversely accelerates as it moves down.
In relativity theory,
that’s why things accelerate toward the center of the Earth. If you
throw a baseball, the curved arc is typically about a quadrillionth
of a second longer than sitting on the ground. The baseball doesn’t
want to go too crazy and fly off into deep space, though, or
otherwise spatial distance would become a factor and the
increases in duration would be offset by spatial distance. This
balance is what determines the precise shape of the arc it follows.
I’m glossing over the
details here, and I want to get back from this digression to my
regularly scheduled program, but I just wanted to connect this
concept of spacetime distortion that you may have heard about to
something you can actually see and think about the text time you
throw a ball up into the air.
In short, physicists face
the problem that their concept of time doesn’t match our everyday
experience of time. Ironically, their reaction is to go even
farther away from everyday notions of time. The leading idea is
that time is not fundamental. How could it be, if it can bend? Just
as substances emerge from atoms, and we emerge from substances, time
might emerge, too. The seemingly contradictory properties of time
might emerge with it. So we can treat time (and space) much as we
treat matter, bringing me back to the title of this talk.

Figure 4b
Just as you see structure
such as atoms as you zoom in on matter, if you zoom in on the
spacetime continuum, we may seem some kind of filigree structure.
There might be a smallest meaningful time duration—an “atom” of
time. These “atoms” of time would be governed by quantum theory,
with its own rules. For instance, there would be no single unique
arrangement of atoms. The spacetime we see would be a composite of
all possible arrangements.
Even these atoms may not
be truly fundamental. Space and time might emerge from still more
fundamental ingredients. This is hard to get your head around. How
do you describe emergence if it is something that occurs within
time? Here’s one way that some physicists try. Earlier, I mentioned
the role that time plays in ordering the world. You can flip this
role on its head and say that the world has an order and time
describes it. We usually assume time precedes and defines processes,
but you could relate processes to one another without introducing
time. Time provides a convenient but unnecessary medium of exchange,
like money.
In that case, time is
meaningful because processes in nature have a particular structure
to their relationships. You can imagine a set of relationships that
is too complicated to describe by a time parameter. So, the world,
at root, may have no concept of duration. That concept, and the rest
of structure of time, may have developed in the aggregate as the
relationships organized themselves. Time does not impose order on
the world, but rather the opposite.
As you can see,
physicists have conflicted attitudes toward time. Let me close by
noting this is also true of our culture. On the one hand, we’re
hyperscheduled and obsessed with punctuality, especially here in New
York. We have come to regard ageing as something to be resisted. On
the other hand, we tell ourselves we need to relax about time, to
spend quality time with people, to goof off online.
Our attitudes toward
space are conflicted, too. Airline travel and telecommunications
have made distance matter a lot less to us than it did to our
grandparents. The modern world is defined by mobility, both
geographical and social. At the same time, there’s an countervailing
attitude that our individuality and independence are important to
us—that we want to keep our distance from other people. And we
obsess about the tradeoffs this involves. We bemoan that we feel
disconnected from one another.
This conflict defines
modern society, and physicists are discovering that it defines the
physical universe as well. On the one hand, time may not matter at a
fundamental level. It emerges. On the other hand, it has to
emerge if we are to exist. Life is meaningless without time. We
fight the ravages of time, but time gives us dynamism and purpose.
On the one hand, distance, too, may be a construct. When two people
are far apart, they might actually be right next to one another,
considered in some broader sense. On the other hand, our existence
requires the emergence of a concept of distance. The very concept of
a “thing” requires it. If space and time had never emerged, the
world would have remained a structureless mush.
Art thrives on tension,
so this should give artists some rich ideas to explore, and
physicists, for their part, can learn from artists that tension is
not something to be explained away, but to be embraced.
George
Musser is an editor at Scientific American magazine and the
author of The Complete Idiot’s Guide to String Theory. He was
a co-recipient of the National Magazine Award for editorial
excellence for the magazine’s special issue “A Matter of Time” in
September 2002.
|