ON NEGATIVE COMPOUNDS: A PARALLEL BETWEEN
PĀNINI AND ARISTOTLE
by Sergiu Al-George
Like many other aspects of his work,
Panini's treatment of negative compounds is not relevant
only to linguistics, but to logic as well. The complex
significance of negative compounds arose in both Indian and
Western culture as a problem of interdisciplinary interest:
expressions like "non-man", "non-brahman" or "non-being"
were thus equally taken into consideration by grammarians,
logicians and metaphysicians. The fact that Panini offered
an interpretation of negative compounds before they received
a treatment in Indian texts of logic has gone unnoticed not
only in studies dealing with Indian philosophy in general,
but even in those dealing with the specific problem of
negation.
The logical relevance of the Paninian
approach to negative compounds is brought out by a
comparison with Aristotle. This comparison comes naturally,
as in both cases identical linguistic structures are
analysed, which belong to the same Indo-European family.
Moreover, the respective analyses were performed
approximately at the same time by two great thinkers who
played a prominent and, somewhat, analogous part in the
development of their own cultures.
In De Interpretation, in the chapter dealing
with "The Simple noun and the nominal compound" (2, 16a),
after a very summary distinction between the respective
types of nouns, based on the idea that the nominal compound
is more determinate than the simple noun, Aristotle contends
that a negative compound like "non-man" is not a noun; the
reason he provides for this thesis is that there is no
corresponding definite reference for such an expression,
which he consequently calls "indeterminate noun". In the
same book (10, 20a), this time in connection with simple
judgments, where the subject is either determinate or
indeterminate, the Stagirite provides further arguments in
support of his thesis. He considers that by employing the
expression "non-man" one is not nearer to, but farther from
making a true or untrue statement than by employing the
expression "man".
Like Aristotle, Pānini discusses negative
compounds under the general category of nominal compounds,
but the latter are treated in more detail in the Astadhydyi.
Here, instead of the general and self-evident statement that
nominal compounds are more determinate than simple nouns, we
find a subtle and rigorous typology encroaching on the
territory of logic.
Patañjali (on II, 1, 6) observed that under
Panini's four types of nominal compounds (samāsa), i.e.
avyayībhāva, tatpurusa, bahuvrīhi and dvanvda, there lies a
fourfold grouping of two qualities, the principal (pradhāna)
and the secondary (apradhāna = upasarjana) which, in the
binary relationship of logical determination, become
determinandum and determinans respectively. If, as B.
Liebich
suggested, we represent the pradhāna by "+" and the
apradhāna by "-", there are only four possible groupings:
+-, -+, --, ++. These four groupings correspond respectively
to the four types in the Paninian classification. The first
two types, avyayībhāva and tatpurusa, are symmetrical
inasmuch as their constituents are in contrast, thus
representing an instance of internal determination between
the principal and the secondary; on the other hand, in
bahuvrīhi and dvandva there is no contrast between the two
constituents and the compound in its totality is related to
some other word of the sentence.
A reference to the samasa classification was
necessary not only in order to appreciate its logical
insight, but also to gain a better understanding of the
negative compounds' structure, in relation to the respective
classification. According to Pānini (II, 2, 6), negative
compounds, called nañ-samāsa, belong to the tatpurusa class
and consequently the negative particle that represents the
secondary constituent becomes the determinans of the noun.
More specifically, the negative particle belongs to the
subclass of descriptive determinatives (karmadhāraya), and
its function is that of an appositional attribute in
relation to a noun. This determinative function is also
explicitely stated by Panini in sūtra II, 1, 60, where he
speaks of the negated noun as nañ-viœista, "qualified by
nañ". As Patañjali observes (on II, 2, 6), the negative
particle is a viœesaka, "qualifier", and is therefore
assigned a definite logical interpretation. In
contradistinction to Aristotle, the negative compound is no
less determinate than any other compound of its class.
Upon a closer examination, this contrast in
treatment would indicate a difference in the way the
extension of a negative compound was conceived by the two
thinkers. As Patanjali explained, the employment of the
negative particle suppresses the meaning of the negated noun,
and thus, in logical terms, it has only an extensive value.
But the extension, in this case, seems susceptible of a
twofold interpretation: it either includes the whole
universe -except the reference of the noun under negation -
and as such is practically infinite, or it is confined to a
definite field. The former interpretation was obviously
favoured by Aristotle, whereas the latter by Panini.
It is hard to find in Aristotle a clear
illustration in support of his own interpretation. In his
judgment theory, the negative expression "non-A" is
considered either as a possible subject or as an attributive
predicate. However, in his treatment of contradiction and
contrariety relationships (Analitica Priora I, 46, 51b-52a),
he lays particular emphasis on negative predicates in order
to distinguish between the assertion of an indeterminate
attribute ("is non-A") and the negation of a determinate one
("is not A"). On the contrary, Panini's work provides a
comprehensive illustration of his interpretation: negative
compounds are freely employed regardless of their being
ambiguous or indefinite as to their extension. According to
the exegetical literature, there is ambiguity only as to
whether the privative nañ in some compounds should be
understood as belonging with the noun following it
(paryudāsa) or with a verbal idea (prasajyapratisedha);
thus, there is ambiguity only as to whether a negative
particle joined to a noun is really a nañ-samāsa or not.
One would be tempted to explain the contrast
between the Pāninian and the Aristotelian treatment by
saying that the grammarian's mental universe, being
restricted to a finite metalanguage, is more limited than
the logician's, but the real explanation is more profound.
For instance, the technical term atin, which is the negated
form of tin, "verb personal endings", should not be taken to
denote the remainder of the technical vocabulary; it denotes
only the primary suffixes (krt), which, like tin, are added
to the verbal root (dhātu). Thus, in Panini's thinking, it
is clear that the extension of a negative compound is
restricted to the field of similar terms. This major
principle is clearly stated in paribhāsā 74: "[The word] to
which nañ or iva are attached [denotes] a locus which is
distinct but similar [to that the of negated word], for thus
is the meaning [according to the ordinary use]".
Patañjali illustrates the ordinary use by means of the same
example, abrāhmana, "non-brahman", which illustrates the
nañ-samāsa (on II, 2, 6). This negative compound does not
denote just any individual, but someone who belongs to the
caste system. Thus, Panini's theory and use of negative
compounds are in accordance with the object language.
Therefore, negative particles are not considered
unilaterally, in their oppositive function (contrariety or
contradiction), but more comprehensively, in a dialectics
where otherness and likeness have equal weight.
A parallel to Pānini’s treatment was
developed in Europe only much later, in the nineteenth
century. Until then, the Aristotelian view had prevailed. In
the Middle Ages every negation was considered to be
indefinite ("omnis negatio vero indefinita est") and, even
in the eighteenth century, Kant qualified a judgment
containing negative predicative attribute as an "infinite
judgment". Only later did mathematical logic produce a
different interpretation, by using the calculus of classes
and set-theory: "non-A" or "A" is contextually limited by
the "universe of discourse" which is a finite basic set.
Accordingly, "non-A" or "Ā" is defined as the difference
between this basic set "U" and the set designated by the
negated term "A": Ā = U – A. If "U" stands for the class of
vertebrates and "A" for that of viviparous animals, then "Ā"
represents the class of non-viviparous vertebrates. "A" and
"Ā" are complementary classes; the extension of a term under
negation is its complementary class.
To say that a negative particle operates in
the field of complementarity is only a different and, of
course, a less explicit way of expressing the dialectical
properties of the negative particle which functions in a
locus coincidentally different and similar. After almost
twenty-five centuries, European logicians attempted to
revise Aristotle's analysis and came up, in fact, with
Panini's own analysis.
The logical purport of Panini's analysis of
nominal compounds can be better appreciated if we observe
that negation holds a crucial place in the science of
reasoning; this logical purport can furthermore be
illustrated by reference to the Indian philosophical
tradition. Should such a study be undertaken, it would
reveal that Panini's treatment of negative particles laid
the groundwork for later logical-semantic developments. The
famous buddhist apoha theory, according to which the meaning
of a word is established by "the exclusion of its otherness"
(anyāpoha), is a case in point: the meaning of the word
"cow" is the exclusion of "non-cow". The "otherness" (anya)
of a word - expressed by joining it to the privative
particle to form a compound - is to be understood as
determinate itself, or else its exclusion would be deprived
of determination. Another instance is provided by
Navya-Nyāya where negative cognition is regarded - along the
line laid down by Panini - as viœistajñāna, "determinate
cognition". But all these topics, which lie in fact beyond
the scope of the present paper, will be discussed elsewhere.